The topic of God’s knowledge of the
future and human free choices has been around for a long time and will continue
to be a matter of considerable debate. The fact that this remains a hot point
of contention within Christian thought should give us a few reminders. First,
given that this is essentially an in-house debate issue, there is solace in
knowing that there is room for disagreement on certain details while still
maintaining Christian orthodoxy (right belief). Indeed, most disagreements
among Christians – Protestants and Catholics particularly – usually involve
differences of interpretation and explanation of certain key doctrines that all
of us hold in common.
For example, everyone believes that God
is eternal. Eternity is considered to be a necessary or essential attribute of
God’s nature. An essential attribute or property is an attribute that something
or someone cannot lack and still be what it is. So with the issue of eternity,
theologians and philosophers disagree on God’s relationship to time, which is
part of the issue of divine eternity. Some think that God is outside of time
and hence sees all events at once (i.e. Augustine of Hippo) whereas some hold
that God is in time and only causes events that are presently occurring,
not events that will occur (i.e. William Lane Craig). So as I said,
there is room for dispute on the question of whether God is in or outside of
time.
The second reminder that I think would
be beneficial is that even though this issue involves much complicated
terminologies and concepts, it has great practical importance for living life
as Christians. All Christians educated and uneducated, live their lives based on
certain theological formulations they have developed in certain ways. So
theological and philosophical reflection on deep, mind-expanding issues can be
a way of helping us grapple with how we live life in light of certain beliefs
we hold.
Another point is that this discussion
helps us fulfill a central command from Scripture that Christ gives to us in
Matthew 22:37: Jesus said to him, ‘Love
the Lord your God with all your heart, with all your soul, and with all your
mind.’ The Christian life is not entirely about displaying acts of
kindness, compassion, mercy, graciousness, concern for the afflicted, or
engaging in prayer and evangelism. Though all those areas are absolutely
crucial for a vibrant Christian life devoted to the Lord Jesus, they are not the
only areas of how a Christian life should be lived. Christians are called to
develop their minds or intellects as a way of exemplifying love to Jesus
Christ. If we want to honor God with our minds, then we are obligated to do all
that we can to sharpen and improve our minds in two key areas.
The first area is in critical thinking.
God is not impressed or honored by sloppy ways of reasoning. We need to learn
how to recognize truth from error and correct principles of reasoning from
fallacies. This is not something we will automatically learn from Scripture.
Why is that? Because (1) Scripture is not a text on logic or reasoning although
it contains areas where that is accomplished and (2) a person may not improve
in his or her reasoning skills no matter how much Scripture he or she memorizes
or studies. God has given us resources outside of Scripture that can help us in
this area. The second area is in seeking to increase in knowledge and learning.
The ability to gain knowledge is a deep component of the human nature. Since we
are called to mature and develop ourselves as the Holy Spirit enables us,
increasing in knowledge and learning is a great example of how that can be
manifested.
On the third point of discussion, the
issue I am raising has some apologetic value. One of the central problems that are
pressed against Christians concerning the problem of evil is the issue of
reconciling divine foreknowledge with human freedom. Many atheists no doubt
would think that the Christian’s inability to solve the vexing apparent
outright contradiction in affirming a strong notion of divine foreknowledge and
human freedom serves as a sufficient reason not to believe in Christianity.
Sure some Christians might retort and say that atheism implies mechanical
determinism in which every decision we make (physical, mental, etc.) is
causally determined by the laws of physics and chemistry. Of course that could
imply that rationality itself would be a farce. How would one ever rationally
affirm atheism if atheism implies the absence of rationally guided processes?
In any case, this area of exploration deserves much attention from Christians.
If we are going to build any worthwhile bridges in reaching our culture, then
we are going to need to do some serious homework. With that in mind, I will
briefly summarize the contents of the book and give some feedback of my own.
Summary
There are four sections to the book in
which each contributor lays out his case: Open-Theism, Simple-Foreknowledge,
Middle-Knowledge, and the Augustinian-Calvinistic view. After a contributor
presents his case, the three remaining contributors offer critiques of his case
in the 3 subsequent chapters. Since my primary concern here is a brief
explanation of the different views articulated in the book, I will only focus
on the cases that are presented and leave it to the reader to examine the
critiques in the book.
In chapter one Greg Boyd builds his
case for Open Theism. Open Theism (hereafter OT) says that even though God is
perfectly omniscient (perfectly knows only and all truths), He does not know
certain events that will occur in the future because He has decided to let the
future remain “unsettled”. On Boyd’s view, if God exhaustively foreknows all
future events, then they are settled and hence cannot fail to occur. Boyd
believes this would be incompatible with human freedom in the libertarian
sense. Libertarian freedom basically says that an agent A does action X freely if
and only of A can choose not-X or simply refrain from doing X. To affirm
exhaustive foreknowledge would be to deny human freedom and would seem to
explain away many passages that depict God as “changing his mind” or
“regretting some actions He did in the past” as anthropomorphic (attributing
human qualities to God). Boyd argues that the only way to preserve libertarian
freedom is to deny exhaustive divine foreknowledge.
In section two David Hunt argues the
simple foreknowledge view that really states that God “simply” knows the
future. One of the problems that Hunt tries to address and adequately deal with
is the problem of human free choice. The problem is similar to what Boyd
explicates in his chapter on OT, namely that, if God infallibly foreknows what
I will do tomorrow, then I cannot refrain from doing that which God foreknows
what I will do. It is what we could call an inescapable fact. Hunt thinks that
divine exhaustive foreknowledge is compatible with libertarian freedom based on
two considerations. First, Hunt rejects the idea that one cannot be free if he
or she cannot choose contrary to what he or she has actually chosen. He
believes this is an unwarranted assumption. Second, Hunt thinks that even if
one cannot choose contrary to what he or she has chosen, that does not prove
that he or she was forced to choose. So Hunt believes that divine foreknowledge
is compatible with being free even though human freedom does not entail the
possibility of choosing to the contrary.
In the third section William Lane Craig
argues the Middle-Knowledge view. This is the one I have been mostly exposed to
though my knowledge of it is still surface level. The basic idea is that God
has three kinds of knowledge prior to creating the world: natural, middle, and
free. Natural knowledge is knowledge of all necessary truths (truths that could
not have been false) like 2+2=4 or all bachelors are unmarried and so on.
Middle knowledge is knowledge of counterfactual statements, which take the form
“if…then…” An example would be “If Ben had not met with Chris Daniel, then he
would not have received the internship.” Or “If Pontius Pilate were governor of
Judea in 30 A.D., he would have freely crucified Jesus.” Middle knowledge
includes counterfactual truths of free decisions by human beings. Free
knowledge is God’s knowledge of the world He has actually created. So
what does this mean? Well a few things.
First, Craig believes that middle
knowledge can explain how God’s knowing the future can safeguard human freedom without
obliterating it. Since Molinism, the view being articulated here, affirms that
God knew these counterfactual truths of creaturely freedom before He
created the world, these counterfactual truths could not have been determined
or been what they are because of God’s will. They are in essence independent of
His will just like the truths he knows by virtue of his natural knowledge.
Second, Craig believes this can also provide an adequate account of how God can
have a strong providential control over history that is usually attributed to
Calvinism while affirming libertarian freedom usually affirmed by Arminians.
Since God’s decision to create this world was based on His middle knowledge –
which already includes future free undetermined decisions – and not His divine
will, God is not responsible for the sin in the world but rather was “forced”
to deal with the cards of counterfactuals of creaturely freedom he was dealt.
Lastly we have the
Augustinian-Calvinistic perspective. Paul Helm argues in three ways that
Christians should give up the libertarian freedom view and adopt a
compatibilist view of human freedom. Put simply, compatibilism states that
being causally determined to do what you do is compatible with your doing it
freely. What are his three arguments? He argues from divine efficacious grace
in the context of salvation, divine perfection and principle of simplicity, and
the logical inconsistency between affirming an exhaustive account of
foreknowledge and libertarian freedom.
The first argument states that if one
exercised his or her freedom to accept God’s saving grace, then he must have
done something to merit salvation. Since freedom involves actions of the will,
and an act of faith is allegedly an exercise of our wills, it follows that
faith has to be a gift from God and not something we exercise on our own. From
divine perfection and simplicity, Helm says that if knowledge of only necessary
and future truths is sufficient to provide a rich concept of divine
omniscience, then it becomes futile to add middle knowledge to the collection.
And lastly from the logical inconsistency between affirming an exhaustive
account of foreknowledge and libertarian freedom, Helm is essentially arguing
the same conclusion that Gregory Boyd articulated in his chapter on Open
Theism.
Some Feedback
To be brief, I found the book to be
extremely stimulating and mind expanding. The authors I find to be equally
brilliant and intelligent in their articulations and critiques of each other’s
works. In going back to my intro, I think this book needs to be read and
discussed by Christians who are concerned about this problem. This book has
challenged me to consider other points of view that I did not really take very
seriously before. This book also showed me that no view is closed to critique
or criticism. While every argument in philosophy will always have critics on
the other side that does not mean that all objections are equally valid. Some
objections might completely miss the mark and some are somewhat on point and
others are head on. I do not know if this is an area where I will conduct
serious reading and research. I have to be really sold on an idea before I
launch into an in-depth analysis and examination of that area of thought. With
that being said, I have enjoyed this book in many ways and will probably read
it many times in the future to improve my understanding of the issues involved.
No comments:
Post a Comment