Monday, June 23, 2014

Is Abortion a Moral Right or Morally Wrong: Bringing it all back

Conclusion

In this blog series of posts I argued that the issue, which divides people who oppose abortion from ones who support it, is based on a critical question: Who and what are we and can we know it? I argued that typical reasons given to justify abortion usually detract from the real issue and focus on irrelevant – howbeit interesting and important – issues. For the pro-life case, I argued from the science of embryology that the unborn is a human being from fertilization. 

Philosophically, I argued – using the acronym SLED - that there is no morally relevant difference between the human embryos we all once were and who we are today as adults that would justify killing us for any reason without justification. I addressed common objections to the pro-life position and showed why they are unsuccessful. I argued that Judith Thomson’s bodily rights and self-defense arguments fail along with Paul Simmons’ and David Boonin’s arguments to show why the unborn are not persons. And lastly I tried to show that Chris Kaposy’s argument in undermining the abortion debate was based on misplaced issues and did not address the real issue dividing the pro-life and pro-choice sides.

This blog series of posts is by no means an exhaustive treatment of these issues. There are numerous other sources one could consult. I hope to have persuaded the person, who defends a woman’s right to an abortion, to at least reconsider his or her position on the issue, even if they have not declared themselves pro-life. 

Citations

1.         Klusendorf, Scott. The Case for Life. Crossway 2009
2.         Condic, Maureen, L. Life: Defining the Beginning by the End. First Things, May 2003.
3.         Bailey, Ronald. Are Stem Cells Babies? Reason, July 11, 2001
4.         Saunders, William, L. Embryology: Inconvenient Facts. First Things. December 2004.
5.         Moore, Keith, L. and Persaud, T.V.N. The Developing Human: Clinically Oriented Embryology 8th edition (Philadelphia: Saunders/Elsevier, 2008)
6.         Kaposy, Chris. Two Stalemates In The Philosophical Debate About Abortion And Why They Cannot Be Resolved Using Analogical Arguments. Bioethics 26.2 (2012): 84-92. Academic Search Complete. Web. 19 Feb. 2014.
7.         Beckwith, Francis. Defending Abortion Philosophically: A Review of David Boonin’s A Defense of Abortion. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 31:177-203, 2006.
8.         Beckwith, Francis. Personal Bodily Rights, Abortion, and Unplugging the Violinist. International Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. XXXII, No. 1 Issue No. 125, 1992.
9.         Thomson, Jarvis, Judith. A Defense of Abortion. Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, 1971. 

Is Abortion a Moral Right or Morally Wrong: Nobody can tell me I'm mistaken!

Analogies do not help the abortion debate

One final objection I will address is not a direct objection to the unborn being a person but whether we can even resolve the debate about abortion philosophically. Chris Kaposy, in his article Two Stalemates In The Philosophical Debate About Abortion And Why They Cannot Be Resolved Using Analogical Arguments, argues for three reasons why the abortion debate cannot be resolved. First, he claims that intuitions can be revised. Kaposy observes that since intuitions can be revised frequently in the face of certain analogies, “… There is a huge impetus to revise intuitions that might be at odds with our position on abortion rather than revise our views on abortion themselves, because our views on abortion are often non-negotiable aspects of our cultural or ideological identities. Thus, because of the interference of our ideological commitments, arguments using analogies designed to provoke such revisable intuitions will be largely ineffective in resolving the philosophical debate about abortion.” (P. 7, Para. 2).

I will focus on the first reason for time and space constraints in that intuitions can be revised. Earlier in the essay, Kaposy said that the platform for the debate started at the different principles that each side based their position on. He writes, “Analogical arguments and the analysis of cases are necessary features of the philosophical debate about abortion because, by its nature, the debate is marked by a conflict of principles.” (Kaposy 88). I want to focus on this area because this is really – I think – the foundation that will affect the rest of Kaposy’s argument that the abortion debate cannot be resolved.

Kaposy claims that there are conflicting principles between the pro-lifer and pro-choice based on killing humans vs. respecting autonomous choices and that appealing to analogies to generate principles shared between both parties is problematic because intuitions or principles for both sides can be revised. If asking “What is the issue?” was the underlying factor dividing the pro-life and pro-choice advocate, then the issue would not be conflicting principles but shared moral intuitions in which one side’s reasons for his position on abortion are not consistently applied. If we define the real issue out of question by focusing on certain, howbeit conflicting principles that both sides have, then we cannot get to the real issue but will end up claiming that principles – which are generated via analogies - are inscrutable means of determining which position is right, given the different approaches the pro-life side and pro-choice side take on the abortion issue: autonomous choice vs. unjust killing of human beings. Kaposy might say that applying the reasoning of the pro-choice, (autonomous choice) to a non-abortion example to exploit the real issue dividing the pro-life and pro-choice, is not helpful because the intuitions/principles I appeal to, in order to change his mind of what the real issue, are inscrutable and cannot be used to clarify or progress the debate.

This objection seems to assume two things. First, it seems to assume that both principles are equally plausible or valid for each party. Second, it assumes that both sides are addressing two different issues surrounding abortion. If abortion is not merely about whether it’s right to kill humans but is more about respecting autonomous choices, then using analogies to appeal to intuitions for the abortion choice advocate – who is about respecting autonomous choices - that will persuade him towards the pro life position is unhelpful because he started at a different platform than the pro-life advocate. If he had started at the same platform, then he would be persuaded by the other guy’s arguments via analogy. But since he has a different starting point, he is not obligated to accept intuitions that are meant to dissuade him from his stance because that is his primary concern. The same could apply to the pro-life advocate. Maybe the wrong question or focus has been about changing one’s mind about abortion and should be shifted to changing one’s mind about the real issue. Perhaps the trot out the toddler illustration is not meant to change one’s mind about abortion – even if it does – but is meant to clarify what the real issue is. Clarifying the real issue may not lead one to conclude that abortion is immoral, but it will or should lead one to conclude that the real issue is not autonomous choice but is rather the humanity, personhood, and intrinsic value of the unborn.

There is a second problem towards the end of the article that Kaposy espouses. He seems to claim that we are incapable of knowing whether a particular argument is sound or unsound in matters on abortion when he claims “The problem, however, is that there is no way to assess the soundness of an argument by analogy independently of your interlocutor’s intuitive response to the analogy. If the interlocutor does not have the desired intuitive response (for example to the Hedonist analogy) then there are no grounds for the claim that she ought to accept the conclusion. Furthermore, as I have argued, revising one’s intuitive response is also a legitimate strategy for resisting a conclusion.” (Kaposy 91).

He seems to suggest that arguments via analogy about moral matters – or primarily abortion - cannot be established as sound independently from the other person's intuitive response to the analogical argument. Basically an argument is sound if it corresponds with the other person's desired intuitions. If the argument strikes against her intuitive responses, then she is rationally justified to reject or not accept it. This strikes me as relativism. If I said that my intuitive responses don’t cohere well with the idea of the law of non-contradiction, then I am not obligated to accept it. The same reasoning could be applied to rape, murder, genital mutilation, and other cases where others would claim that are well-established facts.

Kaposy seems to make the notion “compatibility with intuitive responses” the criterion as to whether an argument is sound or unsound. The problem is that he seemed to only apply that to moral or metaphysical cases that include abortion or killing in certain contexts. He also seems to endorse some sort of agnosticism regarding the moral issue of abortion and claims that the default position should be given to the pro-choice position.

There are several problems with this. First, it’s question begging. Granting the right to an abortion presupposes some view of what the fetus is and whether it deserves a right to life. It is not a neutral position. Second, there are counter-examples that reveal the absurdity of this position. First, suppose we said that the default position on the issue of rape should be granted to the rapist since we cannot decide whether rape is morally wrong or not. What would that say regarding our view of the victim? What about slavery? Suppose President Lincoln issued an order in declaring a law granting the right to own slaves while saying he is agnostic about whether slavery is morally permissible. Such a position is contradictory.

Is Abortion a Moral Right or Morally Wrong: Meet your Beloved David Boonin

Organized Cortical Brain activity

Philosopher David Boonin who is a prominent advocate of abortion rights, is in my opinion, one of the most sophisticated defenders of abortion rights out of the authors I have read. He is somewhat different from most abortion rights advocates in that he wants to craft an argument that will support abortion rights but will avoid the pitfall of infanticide. Since most arguments that deny the personhood of the unborn could very well be used to justify infanticide, Boonin does not want to go that route. What he will do is argue that even though both the unborn and newborn are not self-aware, the newborn is a person because it has a certain cortical brain activity that allows it to have desires. Once it has the ability to have desires, it can desire a right to life and hence have a right to life. We might call this the “desire” argument for convenience. Boonin’s argument, as outlined in Francis Beckwith’s essay Defending Abortion Philosophically: A Review of David Boonin’s A Defense of Abortion, can be seen as follows:

A. Organized cortical brain activity must be present in order for a being to be capable of conscious experience.
B. Prior to having a conscious experience, a being has no desires,
C. Desires (as understood in Boonin’s taxonomy; see below) are necessary in order for a being to have a right to life.
D. The fetus acquires organized cortical brain activity between 25 and 32 weeks gestation,
E. Therefore, the fetus has no right to life prior to organized cortical brain activity.

In the essay, Boonin makes several key distinctions between having certain desires: occurrent, dispositional, ideal, and actual desires. Occurrent desires are desires you have and are directly aware of them. For example I have the occurrent desire to finish this paper. However, you have a dispositional desire “if it is a desire that you do have right now even if you are not thinking about at just this moment, such as your desire to live a good long life.” (Beckwith 186) Ideal desires are ones you have if you had additional information that would alter your actual desires. An example would be if you walked outside by the pool and there was an anaconda within 5 feet from you. But you had no idea. Ideally, you desire to be out of the area because your life could be in danger even though your actual desire is to be by the pool. The unborn, unlike newborns and people temporarily in comas, does not have dispositional or ideal desires since it lacks the organized cortical brain activity. Hence, killing the unborn is permissible but it would not be permissible to kill newborns or comatose people.

There are two responses Beckwith gives to Boonin’s argument but I will only focus on one for the sake of time. Beckwith claims that Boonin’s argument cannot account for possible indoctrination of someone to no longer believe they have a right to life. Beckwith writes, “a person, such as a slave, may be indoctrinated to believe he has no interests, but he still has a prima facie right not to be killed, even if he has no conscious desire for, or interest in, a right to life. Even if the slave is never killed, we would think that he has been harmed precisely because his desires and interests have been obstructed from coming to fruition.” (Beckwith 187). But Boonin might respond by saying that the slave did have a right to life because he had ideal desires, which included the right to life, even though his actual or occurrent desires ran in the opposite direction.

But there seems to be a more serious objection for Boonin’s desire account for personhood. Beckwith illustrates this well: “Imagine that you own one of these indoctrinated slaves and she is pregnant with a fetus that has not reached the point of organized cortical brain activity. Because you have become convinced that Boonin’s view of desires is correct, and this you are starting to have doubts about the morality of indoctrinating people with already organized cortical brain activity to become slaves, you hire a scientist who is able to alter the fetus’s brain development in such a way that its organized cortical brain activity prevents the fetus from ever having desires for liberty or a right to life.” (Beckwith 188). As a result of this operation, the fetus’s potential and basic capabilities to form into a more mature human being who will eventually have desires and possess organized cortical brain activity will never come to pass.

If Boonin is right that desires determine whether one has a right to life, and since the fetus’s brain structure was deliberately altered so as to prevent it from having desires, it follows that the fetus was not harmed in what happened. Was the fetus in fact harmed by this operation? I would say yes but how would Boonin account for the wrongness of this act? Because according to his account of personhood, it is precisely the presence of organized cortical brain activity that establishes the capacity for the fetus to have desires and a right to life. But prior to that stage, the fetus does not have any desires or interests for anything and hence cannot be harmed because it does not have the present desire not to be harmed or killed. Only persons who have interests or desires not to be harmed – whether actual or dispositional – cannot be harmed or killed without moral justification. But since the fetus lacked all of these qualities, it was not harmed by the surgery and it was not deprived of anything since it did not have desires, if you accept Boonin’s argument for desires grounding a right to life.


To make it even more absurd, suppose you had a mother who intentionally wanted to give birth to three children who had no desires for anything since their brain structure was operated upon in such a way so as to prevent any desire capable state of ever arising prior to their reaching organized cortical brain activity. And after giving birth to them, she kills them, harvests their eggs, and donates them to the Center for Disease Control for research. Has she done something morally wrong? Yes because she deliberately consented to an operation that blocked the fetuses’ developmental capacity of being directly able to desire anything and hence she hindered its growth process. On the substance view of persons, the fetus was harmed because its potential growth was blocked from coming to completion, not merely because it failed to reach the state of desiring anything. At the end of the day, Boonin’s account for personhood fails for justifying why intentionally preventing someone from ever having desires prior to reaching organized cortical brain activity would be morally wrong or why it would harm the subject in question.

Is Abortion a Moral Right or Morally Wrong: Lack self-awareness? Failed the personhood test!

Scott Klusendorf discusses the issue of whether the unborn embryo or fetus is a person and interacts with an abortion rights proponent who so happens to be religious. Paul D. Simmons, who authored “Personhood, the Bible, and the Abortion Debate” published by the Religious Coalition for Reproductive Choice, argues that even though the unborn is biologically a human being, it is not a person for the fact it does not possess self-awareness and consequently is not made in God’s image. He writes, “No one can deny the continuum from fertilization to maturity and adulthood. That does not mean, however, that every step on the continuum has the same value or constitutes the same entity… A person has capacities of reflective choice, relational responses, social experience, moral perception, and self-awareness.” (Ibid.) 

And consequently, since the unborn does not possess these attributes, he is not a person. There are at least two problems with this argument. First, infanticide is morally permissible on these grounds. Peter Singer, an infanticide proponent, scolds abortion rights advocates for being inconsistent in their measuring rod for determining who is a person and who isn’t. In Practical Ethics he writes, “ If self-awareness makes one valuable as a person, and newborns, like fetuses, lack that property, it follows that the fetus and newborn are both disqualified. You can’t draw an arbitrary line at birth and spare the newborn.” (Singer 169-171).

Moreover, I think we have an argument that reveals the absurdity of this criterion for personhood:
  •     Any entity that lacks the immediate capacity for consciousness is not a person and may be killed without the need for morally justifying reasons.
  • ·      Unborns, newborns, toddlers, comatose, and victims of irreversible brain damage lack the immediate capacity for consciousness.
  • ·      Therefore unborns, newborns, toddlers, comatose, and victims of irreversible brain damage are not persons and may be killed without the need for morally justifying reasons.

Unless one is prepared to pronounce other post-born entities as not persons and justify killing them via whatever means possible or conducive, I insist that the self-awareness criterion be put to rest. But in any case, there are two mistakes I observe in the argument from self-awareness. First, the argument equivocates on the notion of capacity. Whenever I have read papers arguing for abortion rights, I almost rarely or never see any attempt by philosophers to clarify what they mean by having a capacity for consciousness or self-awareness. There are two kinds of capacities in being able to do something: basis or inherent and immediate or direct. To have the basic capacity to do something is being enabled to do that act by virtue of the kind of thing you are and the possession of certain innate features that potentially ground that ability. Let me give an example.

I have an inherent capacity to shoot a basketball because I have hands, arms, legs, and muscles. But just because I have the basic capacity to shoot a basketball with my arms, hands, and jump with my leg muscles does not mean I can exercise that ability immediately. I possibly have not exercised those bodily parts to the extent to where I have enough strength to actually shoot a basketball. The same reasoning can be applied to learning and speaking new language. I have the basic capacity to learn and speak a new language because I have a mind, can read, and can speak. But just because I have those features doesn’t entail that I can learn and speak a language immediately. I will have to read, practice memorizing and speaking certain words as I learn new words along the way. Likewise for the unborn, if lacking the immediate ability to exercise self-awareness disqualifies it from being a person, then I am disqualified from having a mind, eyes, and mouth simply because I cannot immediately speak a new language. But that is absurd.

Even more fundamentally, there is another flaw in this criterion from personhood. The argument takes it for granted that a basic capacity for any development or exercisable property is already present in the unborn. Let me explain. In saying that because the unborn does not possess the immediate capacity to exercise self-awareness, and claiming it is not a person, the argument has decided that having a certain nature that grounds certain abilities is irrelevant as to whether such abilities will ever arise. In other words, the unborn has the potential to exercise these properties even though it cannot currently exercise them. Were it not for the unborn having a certain nature that grounded these abilities to even be possible or potential, these properties or abilities would never come about. The ability to exercise these properties could be seen as a sign of growth, maturity, or improvement that enhances the unborn’s level of function.


It would be almost like saying that even though I can shoot a basketball; I currently cannot dunk a ball into the hoop. I have the potential to do that because of the kind of body I have and because with enough hard work I might be able to do that. But without having a body or being able to exercise, I will never be able to dunk. The same applies to the unborn.