Monday, June 23, 2014

Is Abortion a Moral Right or Morally Wrong: The Argument from Bodily Rights

Proponents of abortion rights typically argue that the unborn are not persons with a right to life. Hence, abortion is not immoral or unjustified. Judith Thomson does not argue in such a manner. She contends that we can conclude that abortion is morally permissible even if the fetus is a person with a right to life. She writes, “ I propose that we grant that the fetus is a person from the moment of conception. Every person has a right to life. So the fetus has a right to life. No doubt the mother has a right to decide what shall happen in and to her body. But surely a person’s right to life is stronger than the mother’s right to decide what happens in and to her body. So the fetus may not be killed; an abortion may not be performed.” (A Defense of Abortion, P. 267, Para. 2) She goes on to provide two cases where a mother would have a right to an abortion while granting the pro-life position: the violinist case and self-defense. In the former, she provides the following scenario:

“ You wake up in the morning and find yourself back to back in bed with an unconscious violinist. A famous unconscious violinist. He has been found to have a fatal kidney ailment, and the Society of Music Lovers has canvassed all the available medical records and found that you alone have the right blood type to help.. They have therefore kidnapped you, and last night the violinist's circulatory system was plugged into yours, so that your kidneys can be used to extract poisons from his blood as well as your own. The director of the hospital now tells you, "Look we're sorry the Society of Music Lovers did this to you-we would never have permitted it if we had known. But still, they did it, and the violinist now is plugged into you. To unplug you would be to kill him. But never mind, it's only for nine months. By then he will have recovered from his ailment, and can safely be unplugged from you." Is it morally incumbent on you to accede to this situation? No doubt it would be very nice of you if you did, a great kindness. But do you have to accede to it? What if it were not nine months, but nine years? Or still longer? What if the director of the hospital says, "Tough luck, I agree, but you've now got to stay in bed, with the violinist plugged into you, for the rest of your life. Because remember this. All persons have a right to life, and violinists are persons. Granted you have a right to decide what happens in and to your body, but a person's right to life outweighs your right to decide what happens in and to your body. So you cannot ever be unplugged from him." I imagine that you would regard this as outrageous...” (Ibid).

There seems to be a key implication of this scenario: the person withdrawing support from the violinist does not seem to be doing anything immoral and yet it would be generous to extend the use of his or her body to the violinist. Numerous responses to Thomson’s argument have been proposed in the literature. I will instead narrow in on one key problem with her analogy. Her mere withdrawing support from the violinist does not seem to be parallel to the case of an abortion. Most people would grant Thomson’s argument that it would not be immoral to “unplug” yourself from the violinist but yet some would question whether it is parallel to abortion. As philosopher Francis Beckwith points out, “Euphemistically calling abortion the “withholding of support or treatment” makes about as much sense as calling suffocating someone with a pillow the withdrawing of oxygen.” (Personal Bodily Rights, Abortion, and Unplugging the Violinist, P. 116, Para. 3).

Moreover, Thomson’s argument through the Violinist analogy would seem to only permit abortion in the cases of rape since the woman was involuntarily hooked up to the violinist without any form of consent. Since a woman’s bodily rights are violated when she is raped, she ultimately does not consent to the pregnancy.

One other case of Thomson’s essay deserves attention. Later on in her essay she defends abortion rights as akin to self-defense. She argues that even if we grant that both the mother and unborn child are innocent and have a right to life, the mother has the right to terminate her pregnancy if keeping her child would endanger or possibly end her life. While most pro-life advocates would agree with Thomson that abortion in this case would be permissible, her argument is nonetheless problematic. She claims that we cannot appeal to self-defense when someone threatens to kill you unless you torture another individual to death. You would not have a right to torture the other person even though doing so would save your life. Why? It is because “In our case there are only two people involved, one whose life is threatened, and one who threatens it. Both are innocent. For this reason we may feel that we bystanders cannot intervene. But the person threatened can.” (P. 269). Thomson’s purpose in this scenario is to show that any view that forbids abortion given life-threatening circumstances for the mother is “extreme” and is to be rejected.

This scenario seems plausible but there is a serious flaw here. First, Thomson equivocates on the notion of threat in her two examples. She implicitly claims that the kind of threat posed by the assassin is analogous to the unborn child even though the unborn child is innocent and the assassin is not. The assassin is posing an active threat to her life, not a mere passive threat that the unborn child is posing. The unborn child, we may grant, is posing a threat to the mother’s life by way of his mere presence in her body. But that kind of threat is passive or indirect, not direct or active. Nevertheless, Thomson insists that we grant that the mother has a right to abort the fetus by virtue of it being a threat to her life and if by keeping the fetus alive her death will occur. The second problem is a progression from the first one. Thomson fails to show why a person, whose mere presence in another person’s life and is a threat to her life, ought to be killed in the name of self-defense if in fact no direct act of violence has been committed.

To borrow an illustration from my friend Lydia McGrew, suppose you and Joe are locked in a sealed and airtight room with sufficient but little oxygen for both people to breathe. Both of you are innocent and neither of you are actively doing harm to each other. You and he are simply sitting together against the wall. But because there is limited oxygen and no external oxygen source to supply more air for both of you to breathe, you end up depriving the other person of needed air just by breathing! Keep in mind that you and Joe are actively doing nothing to each other but simply sitting there. But when you breathe, that reduces the amount of oxygen the other person needs to survive and the same applies to you. His presence and simply breathing poses a threat to your life and you pose a threat to Joe’s life by virtue of simply being there and breathing air. Would you be morally justified in strangling Joe to save some additional air for yourself? Of course not and neither would Joe though it would be beneficial to either of you to kill the other person to save additional oxygen. For these reasons, even if we grant that abortion is morally permissible when the mother’s life is in danger, Thomson has not shown that to be the case by her argument from self-defense.

No comments:

Post a Comment