Analogies do not help the abortion
debate
One final objection I will address is
not a direct objection to the unborn being a person but whether we can even
resolve the debate about abortion philosophically. Chris Kaposy, in his article
Two Stalemates In The Philosophical
Debate About Abortion And Why They Cannot Be Resolved Using Analogical
Arguments, argues for three reasons why the abortion debate cannot be
resolved. First, he claims that intuitions can be revised. Kaposy observes that
since intuitions can be revised frequently in the face of certain analogies, “…
There is a huge impetus to revise intuitions that might be at odds with our
position on abortion rather than revise our views on abortion themselves,
because our views on abortion are often non-negotiable aspects of our cultural
or ideological identities. Thus, because of the interference of our ideological
commitments, arguments using analogies designed to provoke such revisable
intuitions will be largely ineffective in resolving the philosophical debate
about abortion.” (P. 7, Para. 2).
I will focus on the first reason for
time and space constraints in that intuitions can be revised. Earlier in the
essay, Kaposy said that the platform for the debate started at the different
principles that each side based their position on. He writes, “Analogical
arguments and the analysis of cases are necessary features of the philosophical
debate about abortion because, by its nature, the debate is marked by a
conflict of principles.” (Kaposy 88). I want to focus on this area because this
is really – I think – the foundation that will affect the rest of Kaposy’s
argument that the abortion debate cannot be resolved.
Kaposy claims that there are
conflicting principles between the pro-lifer and pro-choice based on killing
humans vs. respecting autonomous choices and that appealing to analogies to
generate principles shared between both parties is problematic because
intuitions or principles for both sides can be revised. If asking “What is the
issue?” was the underlying factor dividing the pro-life and pro-choice
advocate, then the issue would not be conflicting principles but shared moral
intuitions in which one side’s reasons for his position on abortion are not consistently applied. If we define the
real issue out of question by focusing on certain, howbeit conflicting
principles that both sides have, then we cannot get to the real issue but will
end up claiming that principles – which are generated via analogies - are
inscrutable means of determining which position is right, given the different
approaches the pro-life side and pro-choice side take on the abortion issue:
autonomous choice vs. unjust killing of human beings. Kaposy might say that
applying the reasoning of the pro-choice, (autonomous choice) to a non-abortion
example to exploit the real issue dividing the pro-life and pro-choice, is not
helpful because the intuitions/principles I appeal to, in order to change his
mind of what the real issue, are inscrutable and cannot be used to clarify or
progress the debate.
This objection seems to assume two
things. First, it seems to assume that both principles are equally plausible or
valid for each party. Second, it assumes that both sides are addressing two
different issues surrounding abortion. If abortion is not merely about whether
it’s right to kill humans but is more about respecting autonomous choices, then
using analogies to appeal to intuitions for the abortion choice advocate – who
is about respecting autonomous choices - that will persuade him towards the pro
life position is unhelpful because he started at a different platform than the
pro-life advocate. If he had started at the same platform, then he would be
persuaded by the other guy’s arguments via analogy. But since he has a
different starting point, he is not obligated to accept intuitions that are
meant to dissuade him from his stance because that is his primary concern. The
same could apply to the pro-life advocate. Maybe the wrong question or focus
has been about changing one’s mind about abortion and should be shifted to
changing one’s mind about the real issue. Perhaps the trot out the toddler
illustration is not meant to change one’s mind about abortion – even if it does
– but is meant to clarify what the real issue is. Clarifying the real issue may
not lead one to conclude that abortion is immoral, but it will or should lead
one to conclude that the real issue is not autonomous choice but is rather the
humanity, personhood, and intrinsic value of the unborn.
There is a second problem towards the
end of the article that Kaposy espouses. He seems to claim that we are incapable
of knowing whether a particular argument is sound or unsound in matters on
abortion when he claims “The problem, however, is that there is no way to
assess the soundness of an argument by analogy independently of your
interlocutor’s intuitive response to the analogy. If the interlocutor does not
have the desired intuitive response (for example to the Hedonist analogy) then
there are no grounds for the claim that she ought to accept the conclusion.
Furthermore, as I have argued, revising one’s intuitive response is also a
legitimate strategy for resisting a conclusion.” (Kaposy 91).
He seems to suggest that arguments via
analogy about moral matters – or primarily abortion - cannot be established as
sound independently from the other person's intuitive response to the
analogical argument. Basically an argument is sound if it corresponds with the
other person's desired intuitions. If the argument strikes against her
intuitive responses, then she is rationally justified to reject or not accept
it. This strikes me as relativism. If I said that my intuitive responses don’t
cohere well with the idea of the law of non-contradiction, then I am not
obligated to accept it. The same reasoning could be applied to rape, murder,
genital mutilation, and other cases where others would claim that are
well-established facts.
Kaposy seems to make the notion
“compatibility with intuitive responses” the criterion as to whether an
argument is sound or unsound. The problem is that he seemed to only apply that
to moral or metaphysical cases that include abortion or killing in certain
contexts. He also seems to endorse some sort of agnosticism regarding the moral
issue of abortion and claims that the default position should be given to the
pro-choice position.
There are several problems with this.
First, it’s question begging. Granting the right to an abortion presupposes
some view of what the fetus is and whether it deserves a right to life. It is
not a neutral position. Second, there are counter-examples that reveal the absurdity
of this position. First, suppose we said that the default position on the issue
of rape should be granted to the rapist since we cannot decide whether rape is
morally wrong or not. What would that say regarding our view of the victim?
What about slavery? Suppose President Lincoln issued an order in declaring a
law granting the right to own slaves while saying he is agnostic about whether
slavery is morally permissible. Such a position is contradictory.
Thanks for this series. I haven't read everything yet, or understood everything I've read, but I've seen enough to think my questions are not answered elsewhere in the series.
ReplyDelete"First, he claims that intuitions can be revised. Kaposy observes that since intuitions can be revised frequently in the face of certain analogies, '… There is a huge impetus to revise intuitions that might be at odds with our position on abortion rather than revise our views on abortion themselves, because our views on abortion are often non-negotiable aspects of our cultural or ideological identities. Thus, because of the interference of our ideological commitments, arguments using analogies designed to provoke such revisable intuitions will be largely ineffective in resolving the philosophical debate about abortion.'”
Again I have to say "I haven't read" -- I haven't read Kaposy, and will proceed just on the basis of what appears above. My questions:
1. Does he hold a concept of a correct moral intuition, that is, a belief that there is or can be such a thing?
2. Does he hold a concept of a correct social policy on abortion or on anything else?
3. If he holds neither of those concepts, is his interest only whether society can find consensus, regardless of whether the consensus is a benign one or a harmful one in its effects (if he would say those adjectives have any meaning), apart from the value of consensus per se?
4. If there is such a thing as a correct moral intuition, no doubt it CAN be revised away if once found in oneself, and, perhaps he would agree, can fail to be found in the first place, but may it also be possible somehow to identify it and base social policy on it?
5. According to him, can our ideological commitments not themselves be intuitions, even if they are also aspects of our cultural identities or whatever?
I have argued that there are correct moral intuitions (and defined "correct" in terms of their contribution to human transcendent experiences), and argued that it is not possible to logically prove their validity, but that they will prevail in the course of human individual and social evolution: http://www.NoTerminationWithoutRepresentation.org/dismantling-the-bodily-rights-argument-without-using-the-responsibility-argument/