Rape
Bringing up the issue of rape in
pro-life discussions tends to be a common phenomenon. In my own personal
experience of interacting with people who support abortion rights for a woman,
almost ninety percent of them appealed to cases of rape to support a right to
an abortion for a woman. The argument from rape would seem to go something like
this:
·
A woman,
who has been traumatized by rape, will be emotionally scarred if she is forced
to carry her pregnancy to term in being reminded of her experience.
· It is
morally wrong to force a woman, who has been traumatized by rape, to carry an
unwanted pregnancy to term.
· Therefore,
prohibiting a woman from having an abortion, who has been traumatized by rape, is
morally wrong.
How
would an advocate of abortion rights defend this argument? Let’s examine each
of the premises. Premise 1 seems undeniable on its face and seems plausible in
its own right. Women who were raped already have suffered deep, emotional
trauma from that experience. It seems implausible to think that it would be
easy emotionally to give birth to someone who reminds her of her experience. To
deny that would seem to trivialize the woman’s experience, which is entirely
unjustified.
What
about premise two? It claims that it is morally wrong to force a woman, who has
been traumatized by rape, to carry an unwanted pregnancy to term. It
undoubtedly has powerful emotional appeal but is it true? I do not think so for
at least two reasons. First, it obviously begs the question towards the
non-humanity of the unborn. As horrific as rape is, let us consider an analogy,
which will clarify why this premise is fallacious.
Suppose
a girl named Allison gave birth to a baby girl and named her Grace. Grace grows
up to be 3 years old. The father of Grace is the man who raped her and worse, was
her best friend. Allison has battled with depression and suicidal thoughts ever
since the rape and has not gotten over it. She finally decides she cannot deal
with looking at her daughter anymore, since she is reminded of that experience.
Would Allison be justified in killing her three year old so that she can feel
better? Hardly so. Unless one begins with the assumption that the unborn are
not human beings, one cannot justifiably defend a woman’s right to have an
abortion, even when she has been raped since they would not consistently apply
that reasoning to a killing three year old.
Second,
the expression “forcing the woman to carry her unwanted pregnancy to term” does
not capture the facts of a much broader picture. Generally speaking people, who
defend abortion rights for a woman who was raped, claim that the woman is too
emotionally unstable to raise the child and provide it with the nurture and
care it deserves. It is not obviously true that “forcing” a woman, to give
birth to someone conceived in rape, constitutes an imposition on her to care
for the child permanently or even to raise her. There is less cost to giving
birth to someone conceived in rape than raising and caring for that child.
Aside
from the superficiality of this argument, there is an important question to be
raised that will clarify the issue and will distinguish two kinds of people. To
borrow this question from Scott Klusendorf, how must we treat innocent human
beings who remind us of painful events? Since it has been argued – and
hopefully demonstrated – that the unborn are part of the human community, it
follows that they are part of the picture and must not be disregarded. It must
be emphasized that rape is no small of an issue for a woman to deal with. I
cannot personally attest to the trauma and horror a woman feels after being
raped. However, we must not swiftly assume that only the woman has rights in
this issue. Yes it was only the woman who was wronged but it does not follow
that only the woman has rights. The unborn has rights because he is a human
being endowed with intrinsic value. Caring for the unborn child and the mother
seems like the most plausible solution.
Now
some might object to this by saying that caring for the unborn child and mother
in being the most plausible solution is only true to the one who (1) already believes
the unborn is a human being and (2) who has not personally encountered that situation.
In other words, if you defend the pro-life position in this issue, it’s only
true for you but not true for the person who defends a woman’s right to an
abortion. Truth might possibly be relative.
There
are three factors to keep in mind. First, it has already been argued and
hopefully demonstrated that the unborn is a human being. I have not merely
asserted that the unborn is a human being but have presented arguments and
evidence for that claim. To claim it’s merely an assertion on my part is to not
deal with the arguments I have presented and does nothing to refute my claim
about the unborn. Second, while it is true that I cannot personally attest to
how a woman feels when she has been raped, it does not follow that I have no
ability to make moral judgments about what she can or cannot do. The claim is
that in order for me to make a moral judgment – moral praise or blame -
regarding someone’s actions, I have to have been able to walk in their shoes or
attest to their experiences.
If
this were a valid criterion then certain absurdities would result: (1) Ordinary
citizens who have never held a political office can’t speak to a President’s
actions as morally wrong because they have never been President; (2) People who
have never been parents cannot, for themselves, speak to the actions of any
parents as morally wrong (even for parents who abuse their children); and (3)
This objection can be turned on its own head because if the person, who defends
a woman’s right to have an abortion because of being raped, is neither a woman nor
has ever been raped cannot speak to what the woman should or can do. Why not?
Because he or she has never been raped! So by their own standards, they cannot
speak to whether a woman can have an abortion or not. But this is absurd.
People make moral judgments all the time whether they are aware of it or not.
The question is not whether we make them but whether they are correct moral
judgments.
And
third, as I clarified in the beginning, claiming that this is a matter of “true for you, but not for me”
confuses claims regarding preference and morality. Claims about preference can
perfectly be true for some and not for others. For example, some like chocolate
ice cream and some prefer vanilla ice cream. Others might prefer a massage
session on a Saturday afternoon than going to the pool. Numerous examples could
be given to illustrate how preferential claims are flexible and are not binding
on anyone.
But
moral claims are not like this for at least two reasons. First, one can improve
in his or her character by the result of certain morally relevant choices.
Likewise one can degenerate in his moral qualities because of certain choices
he or she makes. For example, suppose I wanted to develop the quality of
patience. If I lost my temper nearly every time I had a chance to exercise
patience, my flaw in that area would increase over time. In fact it would bring
certain costs to my life that would have broader implications. It might cost me
a job (for losing my cool too many times at a fellow employee), a relationship
(being too pushy for him or her to improve in certain areas), or even the
possibility of further growth itself. One does not degenerate or become more
virtuous in his preferential choices. I do not improve my character by choosing
to play a video game instead of watching a cartoon. For this reason,
preferential choices are not identical to moral choices.
Second,
moral claims are truth claims or propositions. There is a principle in logic
called the Principle of Bivalence, which states that any given proposition must
be either true or false. A proposition is basically an assertion that can be
falsified. A proposition can be shown to be false if it contradicts empirical
observations or contains a contradiction. Moral claims such as “It is wrong to
torture babies for fun”, “Using people as means to an end is wrong”, and “
Killing a defenseless human being is wrong” are all propositions and hence must
be dealt with on the basis of moral intuitions and arguments. To claim that
moral statements are mere personal opinions is to resort to an outmoded
epistemology (theory of knowledge) known as Verificationism.
Verificationism
was a theory of knowledge that was championed by the famous philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein
and others known as the Logical Positivists. The theory basically claimed that
for a statement to be meaningful (that is capable of being proven true or
false) it has to be verifiable by the scientific method or five senses. If a
statement failed that criterion, then it was not merely false but just a garble
of words. This principle eliminated metaphysical, theological, aesthetic,
moral, and even scientific beliefs. It has barely any representatives on the
contemporary scene – with the exception of Alex Rosenberg - and was later
rejected for two reasons. First, it was far too restrictive in what it
considered to be real knowledge. Adopting this principle would require cutting
out the vast majority of beliefs people generally hold to in everyday life. But
second, even worse, this principle was self-refuting. The statement “All
statements not verified by the five senses are meaningless” is not itself
verifiable by the five senses. There is no empirical test that one could run to
verify that statement as true. So, by its own criterion, it itself is
meaningless!
So claiming
it is my own opinion that the unborn are human beings is unjustified and
unwarranted. Second, while it is true that I cannot personally attest to how a
woman feels when she has been raped, it does not follow that I have no ability
to make moral judgments about what she can or cannot do. And third, claiming
that this is a matter of “true for you, but not for me” confuses claims
regarding preference and morality.
No comments:
Post a Comment