Introduction
It has become very popular nowadays to exalt
the ambitions of scientific discovery, especially when it concerns human
flourishing. In all fairness, scientific knowledge and discovery has produced
much good for human beings in the world. But now science is taken to be more
than merely a successful enterprise but almost the very measure for qualitative
improvements on human existence. Ethical judgments and reasoning must submit to
the dictates of scientific discovery and knowledge if it’s to be granted a hearing
or have any reasonable defense for any ethical claim. But as we shall see soon,
science alone has no ability to do all the work in evaluating the proper
recourse for moral judgment and decision-making because ethical notions of
rights and human flourishing are tightly tethered to metaphysical and epistemological
assumptions (rightly or wrongly) regarding the nature of human beings and what
can be known about them in an objective sense.
In this essay I will accomplish four tasks.
First, I will Carol Kahn’s utilitarian ethical framework based on future
entitlements and who would be part of the future beneficiaries. Second, I will
allude to a grisly scenario concerning human beings at the embryonic stage of
development that Kahn proposes. Third, I will analyze two understandings of harm
as she articulates it towards the end of her article and lastly apply these
understandings to the abortion issue.
Carol
Kahn’s Utilitarian Ethical Framework Based on Future Entitlements
Kahn starts off by prompting us to examine how
we should formulate and understand our ethical responsibilities in terms of the
future when she writes, “To develop an ethics for the future, we must know what
the future holds in store for us.” (P.14) It is relatively uncontroversial that
we should examine what the future holds for us now to develop proper ethical
procedures towards moving to the future. But there is an underlying question
that must be answered for Kahn to make her case: Who counts as one of us? As we
will see later, Kahn seems to give the impression that only human beings who
seem to have an interest for or desire their future are part of the future
plans we need to respect and treat with dignity when she starts discussing
issues of cloning and other procedures. But in any case the utilitarian
principle is fairly straightforward: given the desire to maximize utility for
human beings who have a future, there is a proper way we ought to go about
treating such human beings now.
New
Proposal for Kahn: Creating Brainless Children
Kahn wants us to imagine the potential
successes that cloning on human embryos would produce if it were in fact
possible (not assuming that it’s not possible). She suggests that “First, an
embryo would be cloned from a somatic cell and then, when the embryo is six
weeks of age, the collection of primitive cells called the telencephalon, the
forerunner of the higher brain, would be removed and frozen. In this way, the
clone would never be allowed to develop the one thing that makes us human- a
brain. Indeed, the clone would never become a sentient being.” (P.15)
Essentially the human being’s development would be manipulated in such a way as
to stop its higher brain functions from developing. This would be almost
equivalent to creating an anencephalic human being on purpose for an
apparent moral good.
The overarching principle is that if it would
benefit more fully developed human beings (i.e. adults) to perform on
experiment on lesser-developed human beings that would turn out well for more
fully developed human beings, then the act is morally permissible. The
rightness or wrongness of that action would not be so much located in what it
does to certain human beings but whether it’s beneficial for other human
beings. Presumably numerous people might argue that it's morally permissible to
abort mentally deformed or impaired fetuses because they lack certain
capacities for value-giving properties like consciousness, sentience or
self-awareness. Because they lack these traits and are deformed and impaired,
they're not persons and aren't harmed through abortion, as the argument goes.
Imagine if we took Carol Kahn’s advice and
applied it to human beings at the embryonic stage of development. If we would
intentionally create mentally deformed or impaired fetuses, dismember
them, harvest their body parts and organs and distribute them - for curing a
disease - to the person from whom the embryo was cloned, would that
experiment be morally wrong, given the fact that we have manipulated its
development in such a way so as to use it as a means for the good of another? Or,
have we harmed the human being by deliberately mentally impairing it so that it
will not become a person with rights, especially if it would benefit
another? If it doesn't have rights in virtue of not being a person because it's
mentally impaired, deformed, or lacks a fully functioning brain – including not
having the right not to be killed through elective abortion - then it neither
has the right not to be used as a thing for the good of another whether through
abortion procedures or deliberately tinkering with its development so that it
will not reach the point presumably when it acquires rights. If human beings
have value for possessing these value giving properties and we manipulate and
obstruct their development in such a way that blocks them from acquiring those
value giving properties if it serves an apparent noble purpose, then this isn't
morally wrong.
No comments:
Post a Comment